Inasmuch as I’ve been in an extremely busy period in my practice recently, I haven’t had time to blog much. But I came across something yesterday that I wanted to pass along.
Larry Ribstein — the University of Illinois law professor who has done more than anyone in the blogosphere to decry the enormous financial and human cost of the federal government’s criminalization of business lottery over the past decade – has posted on SSRN a new paper that he has been working on for some time – Agents Prosecuting Agents:
Significant questions have been raised concerning the efficiency of criminalizing agency costs and the problems of excessive prosecution of crimes committed by corporate agents. This paper provides a new perspective on these questions by analyzing them from the perspective of agency cost theory. It shows that there are close analogies between the agency costs associated with prosecutors in corporate crime cases and those of the agents being prosecuted. The important difference between the two contexts is that prosecutors are not subject to many of the standard mechanisms for dealing with corporate agency costs. An implication of this analysis is that society must decide if prosecuting corporate agents is worth incurring the agency costs of prosecutors. [. . .]
This paper contributes to this debate by approaching the subject from the perspective of agency theory and analogizing abuses of power by prosecutors to those of corporate agents. It shows that prosecutors’ conduct involves many of the same agency cost problems as the corporate conduct they are prosecuting. At the same time, the sort of market and institutional mechanisms that can constrain corporate agents may not be effective for prosecutorial agents. Moreover, the particular challenges of corporate criminal prosecutions exacerbate prosecutorial agency costs in this context.
This agency analysis illuminates whether and to what extent corporate agency costs should be criminalized. It shows that if the criminal justice system is to be used to punish corporate agents for harm they cause in the course of their employment, then society must be prepared to tolerate increased costs associated with delegating discretion to its own agents, those who prosecute these crimes. Prosecutorial agency costs, in turn, must be taken into account in designing and weighing the costs and benefits of criminal liability of corporate agents. [. . .]
The agency costs associated with prosecution of corporate crime are at least as consequential as those related to the crimes being prosecuted. This matters for at least two reasons. First, combining analyses of the two types of agency costs sheds light on how to appropriately constrain excessive or misguided corporate prosecutions. Second, prosecutorial agency costs bear on the extent to which the conduct of corporate agents should be criminalized at all given the weak constraints on prosecutorial conduct in enforcing the criminal law. The criminal laws may provide significant deterrence of corporate agents’ misconduct that other mechanisms cannot fully supply. However, we should not assume that it is socially valuable to use the criminal laws to ensure totally loyal corporate agents unless we are ready to demand similar perfection from our prosecutors.
We in Houston know all about the implications of the problem that Professor Ribstein addresses.